The Infinite Art of Barcelona

I spent part of the last two weeks savoring the art and architecture of Barcelona, entranced by the work of two artistic giants of Catalonia: Joan Miró and Antoni Gaudí. Both artists seem to revel in dualities. They take the straight lines of the manmade world and bend them. They take the unruly forms of nature and impose upon them an order. They seek to contain the universe in a box, to express infinity in their necessarily finite works.

This is already too much writing from me. Simply enjoy the words and works of these two artists. (The Miró here is all from the Fundació Joan Miró and the Gaudí from the Sagrada Família.)

Look for the noise hidden in silence, the movement in immobility, life in inanimate things, the infinite in the finite, forms in a void, and myself in anonymity.

-Joan Miró

miro_towards_infinity
-Towards Infinity, Joan Miró

miro-1

miro-2

The straight line is the expression of the infinite.

-Antoni Gaudí

barca2-1

The straight line belongs to Man. The curved line belongs to God.

-Antoni Gaudí

barca1-1

barca-1

Measuring IV: The measure problem

I’m traveling this week, so we have a guest post from the inimitable Ashutosh Kumar. Enjoy!


In Measuring II: The limits of measurability, we saw that there is no measure satisfying properties 1-6 that could be defined on all subsets of  \mathbb{R}. Relaxing one or more of these properties leads to some very interesting problems. Well discuss one such variation today which is obtained by dropping the shift-invariance requirement.

The measure problem: Is it possible to assign to every subset A of the unit interval [0, 1] a value m(A) such that the following requirements hold?
(1)  For every A \subseteq [0, 1],  0 \leq m(A) \leq 1 
(2)  m([0, 1]) = 1
(3)  For every  a \in [0, 1], m(\{a\}) = 0 
(4)  For every sequence  \langle A_n : n \geq 1 \rangle of pairwise disjoint subsets of [0, 1], m(\bigcup_{n \geq 1} A_n) = \sum_{n \geq 1} m(A_n)

Banach and Kuratowski made an important early contribution to this problem in 1928. They showed that if we assume that the Continuum Hypothesis is true, then there is no such measure. We have seen the Continuum Hypothesis before, but we will use it here in a the following form:

Continuum Hypothesis: There is a linear ordering \prec of [0, 1] that satisfies: For every x \in [0, 1], the set \{y \in [0, 1]: y \prec x\} of \prec-predecessors of x is countable.

Kuratowski later writes:

As I recall, it was sometime around 1928/1929, during one of my many discussions with Banach in the Scottish Cafe, that we got interested in the so called measure problem stated many years before by Hausdorff and still unresolved at the time. During a many-hour discussion we tried to tried to attack the problem in various ways, unsuccessfully. I got home around midnight. But I couldnt fall asleep until I had found a solution (to my great joy). I met Banach the following morning. “You know Stefan, Ive solved Hausdorff’s problem.” “So have I,” said Banach. What is more, it turns out my reasoning and Banach’s were almost identical: it was essentially a continuation of our discussion in the cafe. Obviously, we decided to publish it in a joint paper (in “Fundamenta”).

A decade later, Gödel showed that the Continuum Hypothesis is not outright false in the sense that if the usual axioms of mathematics are consistent, then they remain so if we additionally assume the Continuum Hypothesis.

Let us prove Banach-Kuratowski’s theorem. Towards a contradiction, let us assume that there is a measure m that satisfies properties (1-4) above. Define P = \{(x, y) : y \prec x \}. P is a subset of the unit square [0, 1] \times [0, 1]. It has the following property: For every x \in [0, 1], the vertical section P_x = \{y : (x, y) \in P\} is countable. It follows that we can write P as a countable union of subsets Q of the unit square, each of whose vertical sections contains at most one point.

Claim: We can write each Q as the complement of a countable union of sets of the form A \times B where A, B \subseteq [0, 1].

Proof of Claim: For each subinterval J of [0, 1] whose endpoints are rational, let A_J = \{x \in [0, 1] : Q_x \cap J = \emptyset\}. Then it is easy to check that Q = [0, 1] \times [0, 1] \setminus \bigcup_J A_J \times J where the union runs over every subinterval J with rational endpoints. The number of such intervals is countable, since it is possible to list all pairs of rationals in a sequence.

It follows that P is a countable union of sets each of which is the complement of a countable union of sets of the form A \times B where A, B \subseteq [0, 1]. This allows us to use a basic fact from measure theory (Fubinis theorem) which yields the following.

Consequence of Fubini’s Theorem: If every vertical section of P has m-measure zero, then some horizontal section P^y = \{x \in [0, 1]: (x, y) \in P\}  also has m -measure zero.

Note that every vertical section of P is countable and therefore has  m-measure zero (use properties (3) and (4)). So there must be a y \in [0, 1]  such that m(P^y) = 0 . But note that [0, 1] = \{z \in [0, 1]: z \prec y\} \cup \{y\} \cup P^y . The set \{z \in [0, 1]: z \prec y\} is countable, so it must have m-measure zero. But this means m([0, 1]) = 0 + 0 + 0 = 0  which contradicts property (2).

This leaves us with the question: Can we show the non-existence of a measure satisfying properties (1-4) without any extra assumption? The answer lies in the hierarchy of large cardinals and we hope to get back to it soon.

Cover image: Postcard depicting the Scottish Café in Lwów.

Measuring III: Paris

The Setting:

Fin de siècle Paris. The 1900 International Congress of Mathematicians takes place in the city. David Hilbert gives the opening address, laying out his vision for the future of mathematics in a seminal list of 23 unsolved problems. First on the list is Cantor’s Continuum Hypothesis, the most prominent problem in the fledgling field of set theory. Motivated by the Congress, Hilbert’s speech, and a venerable professor receptive to Cantor’s radical ideas, three brilliant young French mathematicians make sudden, bold advances in set theory and analysis, changing mathematics forever in just a few short years.

The characters:

Camille Jordan. A respected Parisian mathematician and professor. Introduces Cantorian set theory to Paris through his lectures. Makes substantial progress in measure theory by extensively studying a finitely-additive measure on certain sets of real numbers that comes to be known as the Jordan measure. Known for his unorthodox notational decisions.

Émile Borel. Doctoral thesis in 1898. Mathematician, socialite, politician. Member of the French National Assembly (1924-1936), Minister of Marine in the cabinet of Paul Painlevé (1925) (also a mathematician), member of the French Resistance during World War II. Introduces the class of Borel sets of real numbers and shows that a measure can be defined on them. Provides refuge to Marie Curie during her scandal of 1911. Becomes frustrated by set theory. Stops doing mathematics in 1914.

René-Louis Baire. Doctoral thesis in 1899. Early student of Borel. Grows up in a poor Parisian family, suffers his entire life from delicate health and agoraphobia. Feels the world treats him unfairly, does poorly on oral exams, is given teaching posts beneath his ability. Defines a new hierarchy of functions that goes beyond the continuous functions that had predominated in mathematics. Proves what becomes known as the Baire Category Theorem, one of the seminal theorems in general topology. Breakdowns in health lead him to leave mathematics around 1914.

Henri Lebesgue. Doctoral thesis in 1902: “Integral, Length, Area” contains many breakthroughs. Also an early student of Borel. Develops the theory of Lebesgue measure and Lebesgue integration. Lebesgue measure is a countably additive measure, extending the Jordan measure and forming the foundation for modern analysis. Strained relations develop between Lebesgue and Borel, his doctoral supervisor, over a number of issues, including the Dreyfus Affair and competition over priority for ideas in measure theory.

The Axiom of Choice. Introduced in the early twentieth century and instantly controversial for its assertion of the existence of sets that cannot be explicitly constructed. The young French mathematicians, who so readily adopted Cantor’s ideas on infinity, feel that the Axiom of Choice goes too far and retreat from their earlier explorations, and, in some cases, even from mathematics. Set theory, seemingly going against the strict rationalist tradition of the Enlightenment that prevails in France at the time, moves east, to Poland and Russia.

Selected Quotes:

Higher infinities … have a whiff of form without matter, which is repugnant to the French spirit.

-Henri Poincaré, rival of David Hilbert and opponent of set theory

Like many of the young mathematicians, I had been immediately captivated by the Cantorian theory; I don’t regret it in the least, for that is one mental exercise that truly opens up the mind.

-Borel

Such reasoning does not belong to mathematics.

-Borel, on the Axiom of Choice

I will try never to speak of a function without defining it effectively; I take in this way a very similar point of view to Borel … An object is defined or given when one has said a finite number of words applying to this object and only to this one; that is when one has named a characteristic property of the object.

-Lebesgue

Preview of Next Act

Cracow, Poland, 1916: Hugo Steinhaus, fresh from his graduation in Göttingen, walks through a park and overhears a stranger say the words, “Lebesgue integral.” He introduces himself to said stranger, who happens to be Stefan Banach. The two go on to found the great Lwów school of mathematics, which revolutionizes set theory, topology, and analysis.

Credits

Quotes sourced from the fascinating book, Naming Infinity, by Loren Graham and Jean-Michel Kantor.

Cover image: Paris Street; Rainy Day by Gustave Caillebotte